The first
critique against the idea of cosmopolitan citizenship argues that this concept inhabits
a fundamental incompatibility between cosmopolitanism and citizenship due to
the inherent definition of citizenship. Indeed, for the proponents of this
view, citizenship is defined by the rights and duties binding individuals to
their political community and needing protection and enforcement by
institutions (Isin and Turner, 318). For them, the international sphere does
not present such a range of rights and duties, nor does it have the
institutions to guard and guarantee their application.
For
cosmopolitans, however, the concept of cosmopolitan citizenship makes sense
within a much broader definition of citizenship. Indeed, citizenship can also
be understood in terms belonging and relating to individuals within a community.
This definition, as opposed to the more formal and legal version proposed by
the advocates of the state-centric view, highlights that people identify with
much wider concepts within a political community. For example, people do not
identify with the rights and duties that they are subject to under their state.
Instead, citizens relate to the fundamental principles of a state such as the
liberal ideology and democracy. And, as a matter of fact, these fundamental
principles are the ones found at the basis of the cosmopolitan ideology and
which have served as the foundation on which was built crucial steps for the human
progress such as the creation of The Universal Declaration on Human Rights
(Adami, 45). Furthermore, although they currently have limited power, global institutions,
(mostly under the umbrella of the United Nations) have been created for the
purpose of protecting and implementing these cosmopolitan rights. The success
of the International Court of Justice in responding to crimes against humanity is
a good example of how supranational institutions can be efficient in handling
major universal issues.
The second
argument of the state-centric view in regards to the antilogy of cosmopolitan
and citizenship argues that citizenship is also defined by the particular
rights of citizens to participate and to have their interests represented in
the decisions of the political community to which they belong. Indeed, these
critiques argue that the international sphere does not provide such opportunity
of representation for citizens of the world, nor do they have the institutions
to do so. Furthermore, this absence of representation and participation of
citizens suggests a lack of legitimacy for global institutions. Indeed, although
the actions and the decisions made by global organizations have consequences on
people’s lives, these people are not presented with the opportunity to
influence these decisions, neither to be part of such organizations (Isin and
Turner, 318).
Regarding this
critique, cosmopolitans argue that globalization, and in particular, the fact
that major events can impact the people’s lives across the world, has
transformed the ways that people think about politics and has foster within
them a desire to participate in global politics (Warf, 279). For example, on
February 15th, 2003, people from all around the world protested
against the Iraq War as they felt indirectly threatened by this decision (Tarrow,
17). Furthermore, this recent desire for people to participate in global
politics can be seen in the increasing number of international non-governmental
organizations (INGOs) which provide a means for cosmopolitan citizens to play a
role on the international sphere. Indeed, INGOs now constitute a civil society
known to have increasingly played a political role in the last twenty years;
particularly by covering political lapse from the state-centric system of
government such as in the context of environmental protection (“Union”). For
example, Greenpeace has been able to influence many environmental protection policies
around the world (“Greenpeace”). Furthermore, by providing a means for
individuals to be part of the global political process, and by representing
people and social movements from all around the world, INGOs also contribute to
democratizing and, therefore, legitimizing the political decisions made by the international
institutions collaborating with INGOs (“Union”).
Critics of
cosmopolitan citizenship also argue that the sense of community, which
constitutes another basis of the concept of citizenship, cannot be created at
an international level. These critics claim that the lack of a shared history and
shared cultural beliefs impairs the construction of a meaningful cosmopolitan
citizenship and, therefore, cannot produce a common political ethic which is
essential for defining the common good (Isin and Turner, 318-322). Indeed, the infinite
diversity provided by the broad range of cultures around the world can impairs
the formation of a common sense of community, present on the national level.
In response to
this critique, advocates of cosmopolitanism, such as Martha Nussbaum, recognize
the role played by education and the media in constructing the sense a
community within a state. Indeed, these two forces select particular events and
information based on the assumption that they will resonate within the citizens
of a community. However, by doing so, they also shape the cognitive map of
citizens, their relation with their state, and their compassion of other
citizens of the same state. In her essay on patriotism, Martha Nussbaum
envisions an education which, instead of being nationally focused in its
teaching, would initiate a global compassion within its students (Van Hooft, 25).
Furthermore, as events increasingly have global consequences and generate
global concern, it is possible to imaging that, in the future, individuals from
all over the world will build a common history around important events for
humanity, such as the Second World War or the nuclear disaster of Fukushima in
Japan.
Now entering
the second category of critique from the state-centric view, critics of the
cosmopolitan citizenship also fear that the realization of this concept will
translate into replacing state sovereignty by a system of global dictatorship which
will ultimately promote the interests of global elites. Indeed, although
cosmopolitanism believe in the principle of a democratic ideal that wishes to
see all members of the global community participating towards a common
political direction, opponent of cosmopolitan citizenship believe that the
underlying mechanism of such development will promote the universalism of cosmopolitan
values and, therefore, the promotion of global elites’ interests (Isin and
Turner, 329). For example, although the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and
The World Bank (WB) were originally created to protect the economy of countries
affected by the Second World War, these institutions are now widely criticized for
reinforcing the current global power imbalance, that is, the supremacy of
wealthier countries over the rest of the world, and policies which polarize global
economic inequality (Makwana).
Certainly,
although cosmopolitans generally do not advocate any means to global governance,
the concern that further powerful global institutions, such as the IMF and the
WB, can promote the interest of elites remains. However, applying cosmopolitan
ideas, such as equality and global democracy, to global institutions would
actually promote further distribution of resources and power instead of
maintaining the current power imbalance and the overrepresentation of wealthy
countries in these establishments (Van Hooft, 163).
On a similar
note, proponent of the state-centric view argue that the universal morals which
design the logic of cosmopolitan citizenship do not subscribe to the cultural
differences that exist on a global scale and stand against the current liberal
tradition to cater rights according to preference of different members of a
same political community (Isin and Turner, 324). These critics believe that actions
from the wealthier countries (usually the ones promoting cosmopolitanism) to
realize the concept of a cosmopolitan citizenship could influence global
politics in a culturally biased manner which would eventually promote their own
interests (Isin and Turner, 322).
However, instead
of imposing culturally bias ideas, cosmopolitan argue for pluralism. This means
that, alike in liberal democracies, their ideology wishes to particularly
protect cultural minorities from the tyranny of the majority (Adami, 50).
Indeed, cultural diversity exists within nations and is nevertheless
accommodated. For example, the Canadian government claims to have built a
national identity on the basis of cultural diversity. However, common
fundamental principles such as liberty and equality bond Canadian citizens into
a common nation. The same logic could then be applied on a global scale.
Furthermore, cosmopolitanism generally wishes to focus on already existing
similitudes amongst human beings (Adami, 58). For example, The International
Bill of Human Rights has demonstrated the opportunity to build strong common
grounds from shared universal values, without necessarily promoting in any
controversial ideas impeding on nations’ cultural preferences or needs.
Finally, the
last category of critique from the state-centric view reproaches cosmopolitan citizenship to diluting individuals’
sense of citizenship towards their respective state. For them, current
political movements should focus on the more urgent matter of consolidating and
preserving national citizenship (Isin and Turner, 317). David Miller, for
example, highlights the importance “to nurture civic virtues within existing
national communities” as, according to him, the attention toward the
international sphere “loosen the ties” between citizens and their state and,
therefore, erodes their sense of a national political community (Isin and
Turner, 319). Indeed, over the last forty years, an increasing disengagement of
citizens in their national political process has been observed around the world
through the lessening percentage of voting individuals (“Voter Turnout”).
In response to
this critique, cosmopolitanism proponents argue that citizens are now
interested in international events due to the impact of these events on their
lives (Warf, 279). Indeed, globalization is undermining national governments’
legitimacy because of their inability to stop global forces such as important
economic development (Brown, 53). The cosmopolitan counter-argument is then
that it is the overriding phenomenon of globalization that is, in fact,
loosening ties between citizens and their respective state – not
cosmopolitanism which merely derives from globalization. Finally, cosmopolitans
do not wish to see the importance of national matters diminishing over
cosmopolitan interests. Instead, they argue in favor of finding a balance
between citizens’ duty towards their state and fellow citizens, and towards the
human race (Brown, 55). As Immanuel Kant puts it, cosmopolitan citizenship
suggests that a “community of humankind [exists] alongside the system of
states” – not above it (Isin and Turner, 321).
The current
skepticism toward the concept of a cosmopolitan citizenship can be understood
as a typical conservative reaction in response to the crisis brought by
globalization, such as the global economic crisis for 2008. In the past,
similar conservative ideas have attempted to prevent the creation of important
global institutions and international rights which are now recognized to be
important definitions of human progress towards a more just and equal world. Despite
these critiques, the concept of a cosmopolitan citizenship is, nevertheless,
more than ever shaping global politics, notably through INGOs and other global
institutions. Indeed, in addition to drastically transforming people’s life and
their experience of citizenship, globalization has engendered the desire and
the need for citizens of the world to play a role in international political
decisions as they increasingly feel concerned by the development of
international issues. For them, cosmopolitanism then presents the possibility
to respond to these new needs by offering an alternative scheme in which
international factors would be more appropriately accommodated and dealt with.
Work Cited
Adami,
Rebecca. "Intersectional Dialogue - A Cosmopolitical Dialogue of Ethics."
Cosmopolitan Civil Societies: An Interdisciplinary Journal 5.2 (2013): 45-62.
Academic Search Complete. Web. 26 Nov. 2013.
Brown,
Garrett Wallace. "Bringing The State Back Into Cosmopolitanism: The Idea
of Responsible Cosmopolitan States." Political Studies Review 9.1 (2011):
53-66. Academic Search Complete. Web. 24 Nov. 2013.
"Greenpeace
Victories." Greenpeace International. N.p., 1 Jan. 2013. Web. 25 Nov.
2013. .
Isin,
Engin F., and Bryan S. Turner. "Cosmopolitan Citizenship." Handbook
of Citizenship Studies. London: Sage, 2002. 317-332. Print.
Makwana,
Rajesh. "Decommissioning The IMF, World Bank and WTO." STWR -
Share The World's Resources. N.p., 5 Dec. 2013. Web. 24 Nov. 2013.
.
Tarrow,
Sidney. The New Transnational Activism. New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2005. Print.
"Union
of International Associations." Changing relationships between
International Non-Governmental Organizations and the United Nations. N.p.,
n.d. Web. 25 Nov. 2013. .
"Voter
Turnout." Conferenceboard.ca. N.p., 1 Jan. 2013. Web. 25 Nov. 2013.
.
Warf,
Barney. "Nationalism, Cosmopolitanism, And Geographical
Imaginations." Geographical Review 102.3 (2012): 271-292. Academic Search
Complete. Web. 24 Nov. 2013.
No comments:
Post a Comment